Wednesday, December 13, 2017

The United Nations and Their Adherence To Just War Theory and Tradition



The United Nations was founded in 1945 as a successor to the failed League of Nations as an intergovernmental organization (IGO) with the purpose to maintain international peace and establish cooperation between nations.  Since its inception, ethical questions have arisen regarding its tenets as compared to its actions.  The paper will focus on the United Nations (UN) as a non-state actor and its role in global humanitarian intervention and the use of pre-emptive military actions against a belligerent state.  Additionally, it will examine the UN’s legitimacy as a global sovereign authority.  It will analyze the UN’s actions in the context of just war theory and demonstrate the inconsistencies in the UN’s actions as they apply to the main tenants of the theory.  
The preamble of the UN Charter states that its primary purpose is “to save succeeding generations from the scourge of war, which twice in our lifetime has brought untold sorrow to mankind.”[1]  To achieve these goals, the UN devised a set of rules that incorporate just war principles within its charter.  The UN is a non-state actor, which would normally preclude its ability to participate as a legitimate authority in global conflicts within just war tradition.  However, in Chapter V, article 24, member nations agree to allow the Security Council to act in their stead, lending the UN legitimacy.[2] 
Many of the articles within the UN Charter contain guidelines which are reflective of just war tradition.  For instance, in Chapter VI, Article 33, the Security Council (SC) must exhaust all peaceful solutions to a conflict prior to authorizing an armed response.  On the other hand, Article 39 grants the SC the ability to “determine the existence of any threat to the peace, breach of the peace, or act of aggression” and decide upon a recourse of action.  Classical just war theory would allow action based on an act of aggression, but “any threat to peace” is vague and seems to be an abstract goal rather than a concrete principle.  Another important tenet that confirms the UN’s commitment to satisfying just war theory is Chapter VII, Article 51, which states that the UN cannot bar member nations from collective self-defense if confronted by an act of aggression.[3]  This mirrors Walzer’s jus ad bellum conditions which allow any nation under threat of aggression to act in self-defense.  With these examples, it is clear that the United Nation’s charter does attempt to conform to just war principles.
A main ethical concern with allowing the UN to act on other countries’ behalf to initiate armed conflict is whether the UN can be considered a legitimate sovereign authority within just war tradition.  Traditionally, the state has been considered the sovereign authority, since each state is responsible for its citizens.  Can this authority be transferred to an international entity?  Several scholars have examined this question.  Michael Boulette examines the debate on this subject between the Archbishop of Canterbury Rowan Williams and Catholic commentator George Weigel.  Williams noted that in contemporary society, the question of sovereign authority has largely been ignored, so he sought to reconcile the UN’s role with Thomas Aquinas original interpretation of sovereign authority.[4]
Boulette explains that Aquinas viewed the right to wage war as a fundamental principle when determining if a war is just.  Aquinas argued that private individuals could not use force for the common good, whereas a sovereign authority could.[5]  Aquinas further explained that rather than wage war himself, an individual should seek redress from a superior authority.  However, the sovereign is responsible for its citizens and is therefore required to act if their common good is threatened.  Archbishop Williams argued that the UN should be considered the only legitimate authority by analogizing individual member states to private individuals.  With this analogy, the member states have agreed to cede control to the UN, who is responsible for protecting their common good.  Boulette expands this argument by stating that
“just as the private individual may not properly resort to force because she may seek redress from a superior authority charged with the protection of a common good, a member state may appeal to the Security Council and the International Court of Justice for the peaceful resolution of disputes…” [6]
With Williams’ analogy and Boulette’s further interpretation, member states themselves have no legitimate authority to wage war without the express permission of the UN SC.  However, both agree that just as Aquinas’ guidelines do not prevent a private individual from self-defense if attacked, the UN charter allows member nations to protect themselves if they are subject to an act of aggression.
            Catholic commentator George Weigel rejects the analogy that equates member states to private individuals.  Primarily, Weigel maintains that member states remain responsible for the common good of their citizens, unlike a private individual.  Weigel argues that “individual nations cannot legitimately discharge their right to wage just wars without betraying their fundamental obligation to protect their citizens and the common good.”[7]  Weigel further contends that the UN is ineffectual and unresponsive to the needs of the international community, and therefore, it does not protect the common good.  On that additional basis, the UN cannot be considered a sovereign authority.  Weigel also asserts that the common good cannot be served while member states are beholden to the permanent members of the Security Council.
            Davis Brown of the University of Virginia also tackles the question of proper authority in just war theory and how it applies to the UN SC.  Brown argues that it is the sole responsibility of the state itself to remedy an injury and that it is wrong to transfer this right to any other power.[8]  Brown’s reasoning on this point centers around the fact that while there are multilateral political forums, there is no single “super sovereign” who can enforce their judgments upon the states.  He reasons that if the UN SC finds a war just, they are most likely correct, simply because the five permanent members of the council have such diverse ideologies that if they agree on anything, it is probably an overwhelming consensus.  However, because of this diversity within the SC, any war that is not found just is suspect because of the veto power of the permanent members.  He contends that many resolutions are not even heard because of the mere threat of a veto. 
Brown further declares that a majority decision does not guarantee that the decision is moral due to regional and national political agendas to which the UN is susceptible, such as member nations voting out of self-interest rather than based on the merits of the resolution.[9]  Brown cites the Zionism resolution of 1975 as a prime example of this mentality, where many nations supported the overtly anti-Semitic declaration to improve their relationship with Arab states and the Soviet Union.  Additionally, Brown argues that the SC supports ‘popular’ states while treating ‘unpopular’ states harshly.  Again, he cites Israel as an example, where they were condemned for their anticipatory attack on the Iraqi nuclear reactor in 1981.  While many of these scholars do argue that the UN should be considered a legitimate authority within the realm of just war tradition, they all agree that some work needs to be done to remove bias and be more consistent in their actions. 
Another moral concern, relatively new in the realm of just war theory, is the UN’s Responsibility to Protect (R2P) doctrine and its use of humanitarian intervention.  R2P is founded on the notion that the sovereign state has a responsibility to protect its citizens and when they fail, other sovereign states have a responsibility to step in.  Bellamy and Williams explained that R2P was formally and unanimously adopted by the UN member states at the 2005 World Summit, though the UN SC has been involved with intervention issues since the 1990s.[10]  The mandate calls for intervention when states fail to conform to global humanitarian laws and engage in human rights violations, such as genocide and other crimes against humanity.  The emphasis is on civilian protection, and UN troops are to “use all means necessary” to achieve this goal.  Evans and Sahnoun defined humanitarian intervention as “coercive action against a state to protect people within its borders from suffering grave harm.”[11]  Like Bellamy and Williams, they clarify that intervention should be used as a last resort and it is only warranted in two extreme cases.  The first is the real risk of genocidal loss of life, and the second is large-scale ethnic cleansing, which could involve murder, rape or expulsion.
Ned Dobos explored R2P to determine if it could satisfy just war principles.  In addition, he asked if the UN SC should be the only legitimate authority who can determine if human intervention is morally necessary.[12]  The first debate is whether the UN has any right to interfere in a matter that is contained entirely within a sovereign state’s borders, since the Charter explicitly states, in Chapter I, Article 2, that the UN is not authorized to “intervene in matters which are essentially within the domestic jurisdiction of any state or shall require the Members to submit such matters to settlement under the present Charter.”[13]  However, Dobos explains that those who debate this issue claim that human rights violations are not solely “within the domestic jurisdiction” of a state and are a matter that concerns the international community.  There is a further divide between those who agree that the UN has a right to intervene in the name of preserving “the peace.”  Some argue that the UN SC should be the sole authority when authorizing humanitarian intervention, while others believe that they should not have that exclusive right—an individual state can also lawfully intervene without the UN SC’s approval.  Rather than solely focusing on whether UN intervention is moral, Dobos takes the argument one step further and asks if the UN’s failure to intervene could be considered immoral. 
Overall, Dobos argues that a sanction by the UN SC contributes substantially to the internal legitimacy of humanitarian intervention by a state.[14]  Principally, this is due to the internal cost, in money and resources, that a single state would need to bear.  Singly, the cost might be too much of a burden upon that state’s citizens.  However, with a UN mandate, the burden can be shared across multiple states, easing the burden on any one state.  Likewise, Dobos argues that UN authorization only legitimizes humanitarian intervention indirectly by helping a state meet the conditions that allow the action to be just, such as proportionality and the likelihood of success.  However, if a state can meet these conditions, does the state require the UN’s approval for it to be morally necessary?  Those who say yes claim that the UN SC approval is needed to keep states from engaging in humanitarian intervention for ulterior motives.  Dobos rejects this argument, stating that even if a state has an ulterior motive to intervene, it does not diminish the good that is done.
While Dobos does contend that states should generally attempt to gain UN approval for humanitarian intervention, he declines the idea that it is a requirement.[15]  He has two key issues with the current operating procedure of the UN.  First, the UN has been largely ineffective in its peacekeeping missions, and he cites Rwanda in 1994 as an example.  Authorization was given, but not enough member states were willing to provide troops to be effective.  He also condemns the veto system, since it “prevents the Security Council from reaching decisions in a truly democratic manner.”  Several scholars agree with this assessment, such as Charles Krauthammer, who asked why the ‘butchers of Tiananmen Square’ had a say in whether America could intervene in Iraq.  Dobos states that if the UN were to become more democratic and abolish the veto system, it would be an improvement but would still not give the UN sole authority, “since the imperative to prevent grave human rights violations will always take moral priority over fidelity to international contracts.”[16]
In a similar vein as Dobos, John Davenport examines the UN SC as the sole legitimate authority when it comes to endorsing humanitarian intervention.[17]  Davenport first scrutinizes humanitarian intervention in the context of just war theory.  Davenport concludes that just war theory does condone such action by making the argument that there are important public goods that need law at the global level to achieve, which includes a minimal list of basic human rights.  Because of this, a global sovereign authority is required to coordinate and enforce these goods (human rights), which he calls the Coordination Principle.  For this coordination to work, the sovereign authority must be democratic and answer to the combined citizens of the member states.  He argues that beyond human rights, this primary sovereign authority would also be responsible for global concerns such as the environment and global marketplace.  Davenport maintains that this argument is in line with just wary theory.  He creates the example of Hitler, and postulates that it is absurd to consider the idea that if Hitler had not invaded any other countries that the Holocaust would not be considered a ‘crime against humanity.”  He suggests that in this case, intervention would not only be morally good but obligatory as well.
However, Davenport argues that the UN does not act as his theoretical sovereign authority should.[18]  His main contention is that the UN was formed after World War II and many compromises were made to secure the peace.  Because of this, dictatorships were allowed on the SC, and its structure and processes are not democratic in nature.  Furthermore, the UN does not have the proper means to coordinate intervention efforts, making them ineffective.  Davenport maintains that UN reform to achieve these goals is not possible because the necessary changes would never be approved by all five permanent members of the SC or a two-thirds majority of member states. 
To understand the UN’s effectiveness with its R2P and humanitarian intervention policies, it is prudent to examine several specific cases.  Rwanda in 1993 is the case that most scholars cite to point to the UN’s failings in this arena.  The UN had the approval of the interim government to offer humanitarian aid and oversee the cease-fire between the Hutu government and the Rwandese Patriotic Front.[19]  Unfortunately, the UN ignored a cable warning of the risk of genocide and was incapable of helping when the Rwandan government slaughtered an estimated 800,000 Tutsis and Hutus.  Once the slaughter began, the UN SC failed to reinforce the NATO-led troops.  Even worse was the withdrawal of UN troops after civilians had gathered at a school seeking their protection.
The first time the UN SC authorized force for humanitarian intervention against the wishes of the state and its central government was in Libya in 2011.  James Pattison investigates the UN actions in Libya to first determine if intervention was warranted and then to analyze the UN’s implementation and where it went wrong.  Pattison states that while Walzer did not believe the intervention was warranted, he disagrees.  Pattison argues that Libya met the parameters of a real risk of large-scale loss of life or the real risk of large-scale ethnic cleansing since Qaddafi indicated in his “no mercy” speech that he intended to “cleanse” the city of Benghazi.  By the time that the UN authorized intervention, there was evidence that the government had already had several thousand of its own citizens murdered.  So, while Pattison argues that intervention was warranted, he denies that forcible regime change was required.
Pattison maintains that the requirements to pursue forcible regime change should be much higher than intervention because the consequences of such an action pose far greater risks, such as more innocents being killed and greater instability in the neighboring regions.[20]  For the most part, in these circumstances, these harms would outweigh the good.  According to Pattison, at first, in the initial stages, the intervention in Libya seemed to have the goal of civilian protection, so the initially it was warranted and morally permissible.  However, “mission creep” eventually compromised the UN’s actions, as the objective shifted toward regime change versus civilian protection.  Pattison feared that it would lead to greater civilian and military deaths, along with the possibility of a worse regime taking over.  Pattison argues that the possibility of a permissible intervention that later becomes morally unsound needs to be assessed according to just war theory.  He maintains that it is not enough to apply jus ad bellum rules solely at the commencement of the action.  Rather, jus ad bellum needs to be reassessed throughout the in bello period as new phases of operations are enacted.  He further elucidates that jus ad bellum should be applied prior to any use of force, such as the bombing of a specific target.
Pattison also contends that long-term consequences need to be analyzed when deciding whether to begin a peace-keeping operation.[21]  In this way, Pattison is adding jus post bellum principles to R2P actions, which are currently non-existent.  He adds that key factors need to be assessed beforehand, such as analyzing the amount of resources available and how much local and global support they have.  In this regard, Pattison believes that the intervention in Libya was warranted as, according to these requirements, it was expected to be successful in the long-term.
Pattison rejects the arguments which state that intervention in Libya was not warranted because the UN had failed to intervene in other similar crises in the past—such as Bahrain, Syria, or Yemen.[22]  While Pattison agrees that selectivity is a problem, he states that the problem is not that the UN intervened in Libya but rather that they failed to intervene in the other cases.  He agrees that the UN needs to be more consistent in its actions.  However, he argues that no action in Libya or anywhere else would be worse because “saving some lives is better than saving none.”[23]
Like Pattison’s analysis of the intervention in Libya, Bellamy and Williams delve into the UN intervention in Cote d’Ivoire and examine its moral permissibility.  The scope of the UN’s actions was brought into question, such as the use of UN helicopters against heavy weapons, which Russia argued did not fall under civilian protection.[24]  In Cote d’Ivoire, the impetus for peace-keeper presence was to oversee the Linas-Marcoussis Accords and protect civilians using “all necessary means.”  However, not enough resources were deployed to be able to properly fulfill this role.  When the results of the presidential election were contested, resulting in a resumption of armed conflict, the UN troops (UNOCI) with the aid of France were unprepared to respond.  Not only were the troops unable to protect civilians after Gbagbo’s forces attacked, but there were allegations that the troops themselves were committing atrocities against the local population.  When Gbagbo refused to step aside, the UN condemned his actions and reauthorized UNOCI to use all necessary means to protect civilians.  However, there was disagreement among SC members as to what this entailed.  China insisted that UN troops should remain neutral, and India maintained that UN troops should not actively participate in a forcible regime change and remain impartial in the conflict.  Overall, the UN was criticized in this conflict for overstepping their boundaries and overriding the Constitutional Council by supporting Ouattara as the winner of the elections.  Furthermore, the UN was unduly influenced by France, causing it to lose its impartiality and ultimately failed in its alleged goal of protecting civilians.
Beyond humanitarian intervention is the question of whether pre-emptive military strikes can ever be morally permissible within just war theory or the UN Charter.  Lauri Calhoun argues that pre-emptive strikes completely fail jus ad bellum principles and its requirement of ‘last resort.’[25]  This is counter to the tenets set forth in the UN Charter.  Furthermore, she contradicts proponents who claim that pre-emptive strikes might be necessary to maintain peace by arguing that they cause the world to be less safe and legitimize terrorism.  She examines the aftermath of 9/11, which led to pre-emptive strikes gaining more support internationally and its context within the United States (US) strike against Iraq.  Prior to 9/11, pre-emptive strikes would have been considered an act of aggression.  Indeed, the unprovoked invasion of Kuwait by Iraq was used to justify the 1991 Gulf War.  However, the notion of pre-emptive strikes is built on the approach of “stopping potential threats before they reach the nation’s borders.”[26]
Calhoun vehemently argues that the US reasoning to enter the war was specious at best.[27]  She cites evidence that the documents that were provided to prove the presences of weapons of mass destruction (WMD) were forgeries, and Chief Weapons Inspector Hans Blix was not convinced of the presence of any WMDs.  Furthermore, Bush stated that removing Saddam Hussein would bring peace to the area and resolve the Israeli-Palestinian conflict.  Additional arguments were made that Iraq needed to become democratic to protect the US from al-Qaeda terrorists that were being harbored by Hussein.
Calhoun strenuously rejects those who justify the war in hindsight, claiming that the world became a safer place after Hussein’s removal.  She states that evidence points to this being patently untrue.  Moreover, the war destabilized the region and insurgent troops have attacked and killed thousands of civilians.  Additionally, the US withdrew from the International Criminal Court (ICC), preventing any indictment for its actions.  She likens the US actions to those of a vigilante seeking retribution as a private individual.  She states that the US retaliation in Iraq is akin to the unjust attack by terrorists on 9/11.  By acting in this manner, the US essentially legitimizes the way in which terrorists operate.  Furthermore, Calhoun asserts that the strategic rationale of a ‘war against terror’ is counter-productive.  There is no ‘finite’ number of terrorists in the world which can be eradicated.  She states that by sending soldiers to “kill everyone who appears to the US administration to be dangerous will actually increase the net number of terrorists in existence” because it breeds hatred and resentment, allowing terrorists to ‘incubate.’[28]
In direct opposition to Calhoun, John W. Lango argues that pre-emptive military strikes are completely in line with the UN Charter and just war tradition.[29]  Accepting (and agreeing) with the UN’s movement toward a philosophy of prevention versus reaction, Lango asks, “Should a UN culture of prevention include an option of preventive military actions?”  To answer this question within the realm of just war tradition, Lango considers four aspects of such an action: legitimate authority, just cause, last resort, and proportionality principles.  The UN Charter, in Chapter VII, Article 49, mandates the UN SC must determine if there is a breach of the peace, act of aggression, or “threat to the peace.”  Lango contends that the presence of WMDs or the attempt to possess them does represent a sufficient threat to peace.
Lango’s first argument centers around UN duties to protect civilians against genocide.[30]  The presence of WMDs, in the form of nuclear, biological, or chemical weapons, poses a real genocidal threat.  Consequently, Chapter VII, Article 39 of the Charter allows the SC to decide what measures it can take to restore and maintain peace.  Therefore, the SC should have the option of pre-emptive military action to prevent a breach of the peace.  Lango does argue that while the UN possesses this right, the UN Charter does not allow any single state to carry out preventive military strikes on its own, as the US did against Iraq.  According to the Charter, member states only have the right to collective self-defense when confronted with an act of aggression, and unilateral pre-emptive strikes do not fall into this category.  This is in accordance with the legitimate authority principle, where a war can only be declared with proper legal authorization.  Since member states sign the UN Charter, they must abide by its dictates (which did not happen with the US-Iraq conflict).  Lango does agree that the ‘culture’ within the UN SC needs to be reformed to make it more effective.  Again, this is primarily due to the veto power of any permanent member of the SC.   
To determine if the presence of WMDs satisfies the just cause principle, Lango examines three criteria that Walzer used to determine if a first strike was morally legitimate:  intent; degree; and urgency.[31]  Lango argues that the definition of intent needs to go further than Walzer’s, which only considered intentional threats of injury.  Lango asserts that a threat of injury from a result of recklessness or negligence should also be considered, just as it is within the Model Penal Code of the American Law Institute.  Lango further reasons that the use of a WMD constitutes a real threat against a state’s territorial integrity, such as with radioactive nuclear fallout or the spread of a plague due to the intentional or unintentional release of a biological weapon.  Lango emphasizes that the presence of WMDs always constitutes such a threat, though he concedes that the magnitude of such a threat must be assessed to authorize pre-emptive strikes.
Next, Lango analyzes the last resort principle, which decrees that non-military actions must be attempted prior to an armed response.[32]  However, he contends that it does not mean that “all possible” measures have been exhausted first.  Primarily, if delaying a pre-emptive strike substantially increases the magnitude of the threat, then it is prudent to cease attempting non-military resolutions.  He argues for a ‘minimization standard’ where the maximum non-military measures are attempted concurrently with a minimal amount of military actions, which would lessen the chance for an increase in magnitude.  He hypothesizes a situation where North Korea sells a nuclear weapon to Syria, which is being transported via ship.  If Syria gains possession of the weapon, it constitutes an extreme threat.  However, since there is some time before Syria gains control of the weapon, they could be persuaded by diplomatic means to relinquish the weapon.  If that fails, the minimal military action could be to board the ship and seize the weapon.
Finally, Lango determines if pre-emptive military strikes can satisfy the proportionality principle.[33]  This principle, Lango explains, “requires that the probable good consequences achieved by war should outweigh the probable harmful consequences caused by it.”[34]  Lango maintains that his minimization rule helps satisfy the proportionality condition.  Since it is not bound solely by military actions, “the line of least harm is sometimes best exploited by using as many non-military actions as possible along with as little military force as possible.”[35]  Therefore, the UN should use the minimization rule to ensure proportionality and satisfy just war principles.
Peter Orebech also examines if “anticipatory self-defense” is valid within just war tradition by analyzing the US preventive war against Al Qaeda in Afghanistan.[36]  Orebech asks whether a terrorist attack by a non-state actor can trigger and justify military actions as matter of self-defense.  If the answer is yes, then the US had a right to attack based on Article 51 of the UN Charter which requires that a state notify the UN of such an action but does not require SC approval.  Orebech, however, counters that the language of self-defense implies it occurs in response to imminent threats that would “cause massive death and devastation…the necessity of that self-defense is instant, overwhelming, and leaving no choice of means, and no moment for deliberation.”[37]  In the case of the US, there was no attempt to negotiate and no imminent threat of further devastation within the US.  Moreover, there was no actual or factual Afghan attack.  Therefore, the US actions cannot be considered as self-defense under the purview of Article 51 of the UN Charter or within just war theory. 
Orebech also discusses the problems surrounding the permanent members of the SC, since it means that those nations have very little to fear from the SC.[38]  He cites the 1956 Hungarian uprising against Soviet rule, where the SC could not act due to lack of unanimity among the permanent members.  Additionally, the SC rarely criticizes belligerent acts by any of these states.  However, he declares that most states wish to avoid the stigmatism associated with defying the UN SC and therefore attempt to use language that lets them “get away with” belligerent actions, such as the case with the US against Afghanistan.
While there are varying viewpoints by scholars on whether the UN’s actions theoretically align with just war theory, most agree that the UN in its current state is not entirely effective or consistent in its operations.  What needs to change within the UN moving forward so it more closely aligns to just war tradition?  Most scholars agree that the veto power of the permanent members of the SC is an immense problem and leads to the UN’s ineffectiveness.  This power creates an uneven playing field because it only takes one member of the “Big 5” to veto an action, even if that action would normally be considered morally permissible by just war standards.  In addition, these members can also act with impunity because the UN is incapable of acting against them, as has been the case with the US war against Iraq and Russia’s attack on the Ukraine or with human rights violations in China.
Davenport proposes that a new democratic federation should replace the UN because it would be far more effective.[39]  The requirement of near unanimity needs to be abolished in favor of majority rule to ensure that the greatest betterment of humanity is achieved.  Furthermore, Davenport states it would “prevent holdouts from putting their local interests ahead of the common good.”  Additionally, all nations need to participate “fairly,” rather than expecting a single country, such as the United States, to bear the majority burden of providing resources.  Moreover, this Democratic Federation (DC) would have an executive and legislative branch that is led by elected citizens from the combined people of all member nations.  The DC members would also be drawn from legitimate democratic states only, though ‘associate memberships’ could be offered to “benign oligarchies or theocracies respecting rights more basic than the right to rational popular sovereignty.”[40]  Davenport asserts that once the might of such a global authority is seen, tyrannical nations will fear it, and he goes a bit far to say it should overthrow dictatorships and supplant them with democratic regimes.
On the other hand, Michael Lipson maintains that the apparent hypocrisy within the UN is somewhat necessary for it to be effective at all and labels this “organized hypocrisy.”[41]  The crux of his argument is that any international authority, including the UN, must respond to the conflicting and competing needs of various states.  Furthermore, it is incumbent upon the UN to somehow reflect its “external constituencies’ inconsistent values and preferences.”[42]  Any replacement of the UN would be subject to these same pressures.  Because of this, organizations, such as the UN, must decouple their actions from their internal organizational activity—when this creates inconsistent behavior, it constitutes organized hypocrisy.  Lipson’s main argument is that if the UN (or any international organization) attempted to resolve all global conflicts in an unbiased manner, it would lead to complete paralysis, since this is not possible with the varied ideologies of its member states.  Therefore, the hypocrisy within the UN is unavoidable.  However, Lipson fails to address the problem of the veto power of the permanent members of the SC, which seems to be a more prevalent issue relating to the UN’s inconsistency and hypocrisy.
In conclusion, the UN precepts, as outlined in the UN Charter, do generally conform to just war principles.  R2P and humanitarian intervention also conform to just war principles when done correctly.  However, the tendency of the UN to go beyond the dictates of civilian protection and take sides in internal conflicts causes it to overstep its boundaries, which was seen in both Libya and Cote d’Ivoire.  Furthermore, most pre-emptive military strikes are difficult to justify within just war tradition, despite Lango’s arguments to the contrary.  However, the biggest issue within the current UN structure, with which most scholars agree, is the veto power of the permanent members of the SC.  While this power exists, the UN will never be an effective or legitimate sovereign authority, since any otherwise morally just action can be overruled for any reason whatsoever.  Additionally, these positions ensure that these members can commit atrocities or unjust wars that can never be answered, further reducing the UN’s efficacy.  To truly be considered a legitimate authority within just war tradition, the UN needs to be abolished in favor of a more democratic entity that utilizes republican principles to ensure impartiality among all member nations and the organization’s governing body.


Bibliography
Bellamy, Alex J., and Paul D. Williams. "The New Politics of Protection? Cote D'Ivoire, Libya and the Responsibility to Protect." International Affairs 87, no. 4 (2011): 825-50. doi:10.1111/j.1468-2346.2011.01006.x.

Boulette, Michael P. "Questioning Authority: Just War Theory, Sovereign Authority, and the United Nations." Vera Lex 10, no. 1-2 (winter 2009): 145+. Accessed October 15, 2017. aurarialibrary.idm.oclc.org/login?url=http://go.galegroup.com/ps/i.do?p=EAIM&sw=w&u=auraria_main&v=2.1&id=GALE%7CA281377268&it=r&asid=bd9bd8a0c7a4bf92b3f07b2b52125fcf.

Brown, Davis. "Judging The Judges: Evaluating Challenges To Proper Authority In Just War Theory." Journal of Military Ethics 10, no. 3 (2011): 133-47. Accessed November 1, 2017. doi:10.1080/15027570.2011.608491.

Calhoun, Laurie. "Pre-emption and Paradox." Global Change, Peace & Security 16, no. 3 (2004): 197-210. doi:10.1080/0951274042000263744.

Davenport, John J. "Just War Theory, Humanitarian Intervention, And The Need For A Democratic Federation." Journal of Religious Ethics 39, no. 3 (2011): 493-555. Accessed November 1, 2017. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9795.2011.00491.x.

Dobos, Ned. "Is U.N. Security Council Authorisation for Armed Humanitarian Intervention Morally Necessary?" Philosophia 38, no. 3 (2010): 499-515. Accessed October 30, 2017. doi:10.1007/s11406-009-9233-1.

Evans, Gareth, and Mohamed Sahnoun. "The Responsibility to Protect." Foreign Affairs 81, no. 6 (2002): 99. doi:10.2307/20033347.

Lango, John W. "Preventive Wars, Just War Principles, and the United Nations." The Journal of Ethics 9, no. 1-2 (2005): 247-68. Accessed October 17, 2017. doi:10.1007/s10892-004-3328-5.

Lipson, Michael. "Peacekeeping: Organized Hypocrisy?" European Journal of International Relations 13, no. 1 (2007): 5-34. Accessed November 1, 2017. doi:10.1177/1354066107074283.

Orebech, Peter. "UN Charter Article 51 and the Right to Ć¢€˜Anticipatory Self-defenseĆ¢€™: Validity of the US Preventive War Doctrine against Al Qaeda." Middle East Critique 23, no. 1 (2014): 53-72. Accessed November 2, 2017. doi:10.1080/19436149.2014.896595.

Pattison, James. "The Ethics of Humanitarian Intervention in Libya." Ethics & International Affairs 25, no. 03 (2011): 271-77. Accessed November 2, 2017. doi:10.1017/s0892679411000256.

United Nations. "Charter of the United Nations." Refworld. October 24, 1945. Accessed October 10, 2017. http://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b3930.html.

Winfield, Nicole. "Global Policy Forum." UN Failed Rwanda. December 16, 1999. Accessed December 06, 2017. https://www.globalpolicy.org/component/content/article/201/39240.html.




           







[1] United Nations, "Charter of the United Nations," Refworld, October 24, 1945, section goes here, accessed October 10, 2017, http://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b3930.html.
[2] United Nations, "Charter of the United Nations"
[3] United Nations, "Charter of the United Nations," Refworld, October 24, 1945, section goes here, accessed October 10, 2017, http://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b3930.html.
[4] Michael P. Boulette, "Questioning Authority: Just War Theory, Sovereign Authority, and the United Nations," Vera Lex 10, no. 1-2 (winter 2009): accessed October 15, 2017, aurarialibrary.idm.oclc.org/login?url=http://go.galegroup.com/ps/i.do?p=EAIM&sw=w&u=auraria_main&v=2.1&id=GALE%7CA281377268&it=r&asid=bd9bd8a0c7a4bf92b3f07b2b52125fcf.
[5] Michael P. Boulette, "Questioning Authority: Just War Theory, Sovereign Authority, and the United Nations," 148.
[6] Michael P. Boulette, "Questioning Authority: Just War Theory, Sovereign Authority, and the United Nations," 149.
[7] Michael P. Boulette, "Questioning Authority: Just War Theory, Sovereign Authority, and the United Nations," 152.
[8] Davis Brown, "Judging The Judges: Evaluating Challenges To Proper Authority In Just War Theory," Journal of Military Ethics 10, no. 3 (2011), accessed November 1, 2017, doi:10.1080/15027570.2011.608491.
[9] Davis Brown, "Judging The Judges: Evaluating Challenges To Proper Authority In Just War Theory." 
[10] Alex J. Bellamy and Paul D. Williams, "The New Politics of Protection? Cote D'Ivoire, Libya and the Responsibility to Protect," International Affairs 87, no. 4 (2011), doi:10.1111/j.1468-2346.2011.01006.x.
[11] Gareth Evans and Mohamed Sahnoun, "The Responsibility to Protect," Foreign Affairs 81, no. 6 (2002): 99, doi:10.2307/20033347.
[12] Ned Dobos, "Is U.N. Security Council Authorisation for Armed Humanitarian Intervention Morally Necessary?" Philosophia 38, no. 3 (2010), accessed October 30, 2017, doi:10.1007/s11406-009-9233-1.
[13] Ned Dobos, 500.
[14] Ned Dobos
[15] Ned Dobos
[16] Ned Dobos, 533.
[17] John J. Davenport, "Just War Theory, Humanitarian Intervention, And The Need For A Democratic Federation," Journal of Religious Ethics 39, no. 3 (2011), accessed November 1, 2017, doi:10.1111/j.1467-9795.2011.00491.x.
[18] John J. Davenport, "Just War Theory, Humanitarian Intervention, And The Need For A Democratic Federation."
[19] Nicole Winfield, "Global Policy Forum," UN Failed Rwanda, December 16, 1999, accessed December 06, 2017, https://www.globalpolicy.org/component/content/article/201/39240.html.
[20] James Pattison, "The Ethics of Humanitarian Intervention in Libya," Ethics & International Affairs 25, no. 03 (2011), accessed November 2, 2017, doi:10.1017/s0892679411000256.
[21] James Pattison, "The Ethics of Humanitarian Intervention in Libya."
[22] James Pattison.
[23] James Pattison, 277.
[24] Alex J. Bellamy and Paul D. Williams, 825.
[25] Laurie Calhoun, "Pre-emption and Paradox," Global Change, Peace & Security16, no. 3 (2004), doi:10.1080/0951274042000263744.
[26] Laurie Calhoun, 198.
[27] Laurie Calhoun, 199-200.

[28] Laurie Calhoun, 207.
[29] John W. Lango, "Preventive Wars, Just War Principles, and the United Nations," The Journal of Ethics 9, no. 1-2 (2005), accessed October 17, 2017, doi:10.1007/s10892-004-3328-5.
[30] John W. Lango, 255.
[31] John W. Lango, 257-260.
[32] John W. Lango, 260-263.
[33] John W. Lango, 263-265.
[34] John W. Lango, 262.
[35] John W. Lango, 262.
[36] Peter Orebech, "UN Charter Article 51 and the Right to an Anticipatory Self-defense: Validity of the US Preventive War Doctrine against Al Qaeda," Middle East Critique 23, no. 1 (2014), accessed November 2, 2017, doi:10.1080/19436149.2014.896595.
[37] Peter Orebech, 62.
[38] Peter Orebech, 59.
[39] John J. Davenport.
[40] John J. Davenport, 531.
[41] Michael Lipson, "Peacekeeping: Organized Hypocrisy?" European Journal of International Relations 13, no. 1 (2007), accessed November 1, 2017, doi:10.1177/1354066107074283
[42] Michael Lipson, 9